Should people with brain
disorders receive different punishment for crimes?
May 25, 2016
Australian
law may be on the cusp of a brain-based revolution that will reshape the way we
deal with criminals.
Some
researchers, such as neuroscientist David Eagleman, have argued that
neuroscience should radically change our practices of punishment.
According to Eagleman, the courts should give up on the notion of punishment
altogether and instead focus on managing criminals and containing their
behaviour in order to keep the rest of us safe.
Is
this a good idea? And is this how Australian judges are responding to our
increasing knowledge of the neurobiological bases of behaviour?
Two approaches
There
are two broad approaches to justifying punishing
someone who commits a crime. The first is in terms of “moral culpability” or
“just deserts”. Crudely, if someone has caused harm, they deserve to have harm
inflicted on them in return.
This
is known as the “retributive” view; retributivists aim to mete out just
deserts, or “just punishment”.
The
second approach is to think in terms of the consequences of punishment. If
punishment might deter or rehabilitate the offender, or prevent them from
committing another crime by incapacitating them, or if it could serve as a
deterrent to others, then and only then, is punishment justified.
If
the punishment will only harm the individual who committed the crime, but it
won’t prevent further crime or benefit others then, on pure consequentialist
grounds, it is not justified.
In
Australia, judges usually take both retributive and consequentialist
considerations into account when determining punishment.
A
clear illustration of retributivism is in the sentencing of the serial killer,
Ivan Milat where the judge said:
These truly horrible crimes demand sentences which operate by
way of retribution […] or by the taking of vengeance for the injury […] the
community must be satisfied the criminal is given his just deserts.
Currently,
Australian offenders are also given the opportunity to make a plea in
mitigation after their conviction for a crime. The aim of such a plea is to
reduce the severity of punishment.
In
some cases, the defence may engage a psychologist or psychiatrist to provide
expert evidence about mental or neurological impairment to suggest that an
offender is less morally culpable for the crime, and therefore deserving of
less retribution.
Neuroscientific tilt
But
some academics, such as American psychologists Joshua Greene and Jonathan
Cohen, have argued that consequentialist considerations will be all
that is left after neuroscience revolutionises criminal law.
Punishment as retribution will be consigned to history.
According
to Greene and Cohen, retributivism relies on the notion that people have free
will. They say the advance of neuroscience will cure us of that notion by
opening the black box of the mind and revealing the mechanistic processes that
cause all human behaviour. Once these causes are revealed, we will give up the
idea that people are responsible for their bad actions.
We
will start to think that a criminal’s frontal lobe impairment caused him to
lash out, for instance, and focus on how we can prevent this happening again,
rather than thinking they chose to punch their victim and thus they deserve
punishment.
According
to Greene and Cohen, this will make crime reduction the only goal. If they are
right, punishment practices will move in the direction advocated by Eagleman.
Case by case
Greene
and Cohen made their argument about the demise of retributivism ten years ago.
In light of their predictive claims, it is interesting to examine how the legal
system is actually responding to the increasing use of neuroscientific
evidence.
We
can get an idea of what is happening in Australia from cases in the Australian Neurolaw
Database, which was launched in December 2015. The database is a
joint project between Macquarie University and the University of Sydney, and
includes both Australian civil and criminal cases that employed evidence
derived from neuroscience.
Interestingly,
the sentencing cases in the database do not suggest retributive justice is
being abandoned when the court is confronted with evidence of impairment to an
offender’s brain.
Where
used in sentencing, neuroscience evidence is often put forward in relation to
assessment of the moral culpability of the offender. It is thus used to help
determine how much punishment an offender deserves.
This
is very different to suggesting moral culpability ceases to be a relevant
consideration in the determination of punishment, or that courts should pay no
regard to questions of desert. It presupposes that questions about appropriate
punishment are important ones to answer correctly.
One
example of the way Australian courts regard evidence derived from neuroscience
is in the sentencing of Jordan Furlan in 2014. In sentencing 49-year-old Furlan
for a violent incident involving a 76-year-old victim, Justice Croucher
considered the impact of evidence of a brain injury some years prior to the
offence, on Furlan’s moral culpability.
Justifying
a sentence of three years and six months, the judge said the offender’s “moral
culpability was reduced, but only to a moderate degree because his judgment was
impaired as a result of his acquired brain injury".
The
judge went on to say that just punishment was an important factor (among
others) in crafting the sentence.
A
more striking case relates to the sentencing of former Tasmanian legislative
council member Terry Martin for child sex offences. Expert evidence indicated
he had developed a compulsive form of sexuality as a result of the effects of
medication for Parkinson’s disease on the dopamine system of his brain.
The
judge imposed a much more lenient sentence than would have otherwise been the
case because of the clear link between the medication and the offending. This
link was said to reduce Martin’s moral culpability.
Slow revolution
We
cannot be sure how neuroscience will affect the law in future. Indeed, there
may even be a backlash against this form of evidence.
What
can be said is that Furlan, Martin and other cases show Australian judges still
consider moral culpability, even in the face of neuroscientific evidence of
impaired mechanisms. They do not move to purely consequentialist
considerations.
This
means retributivism is still alive and well, and just punishment still matters
to Australian courts. So, at least for now, the impact of neuroscience is not
revolutionary.
https://theconversation.com/my-brain-made-me-do-it-will-neuroscience-change-the-way-we-punish-criminals-57571
No comments:
Post a Comment